Advances in medical research mean we have come to grips with numerous diseases and health conditions over the decades. But, like a game of whack-a-mole, you solve one set of problems to only have other, often more complex problems take their place. There is valid criticism to be had of medicine and its reductionist approach and What Is Health? sees neurobiologist Peter Sterling offer a critique grounded in physiology.
What Is Health?: Allostasis and the Evolution of Human Design, written by Peter Sterling, published by MIT Press in December 2019 (paperback, 257 pages)
Much medical thinking and education, writes Sterling, revolves around homeostasis: self-correcting negative feedback loops, comparable to the thermostat in your house. These allow the body to regulate physiological processes, e.g. blood pressure, without involving the brain. However, he found that many endocrine cells, those that release hormones, do have nerve endings terminating on them. Homeostasis is part of the story, but “error-correcting feedback offers no basis for a full model of human design” (p. xxx*). Together with Joseph Eyer, he coined the term allostasis in the 1980s: the brain is involved by predicting the body’s needs and mobilising resources to meet expected demand, temporarily up- or downregulating processes when an organism’s environment changes. In simple terms, homeostasis corrects, allostasis predicts. This also gives us Sterling’s definition of what health is: “the capacity to respond optimally to fluctuations in demand” (p. 154).
This idea has been criticised from various sides as resulting from too narrow a reading of homeostasis, “a travesty that has taken root in textbooks and is widely taught to students as the only kind of control system“, that is not offering anything “that was not already apparent, or at least readily derivable, from an accurate reading of the original concept of homeostasis“. I am receptive to such criticism. Though I was not trained as a physiologist, my layman biologist understanding of it is that e.g. a healthy blood pressure already falls between a range of values and that what is considered optimal depends on whether you are at rest or exercising. Do we really need allostasis as a separate concept? Especially Carpenter is fierce in his criticism: “there is a need to reassert the unitary nature of homeostasis and the variety of forms it can take, so that we are not obliged to reinvent what was common knowledge even 30 years ago, nor to introduce artificial distinctions and boundaries within a field that is in truth perfectly unified.“
Having read the rest of this book, however, I am not sure that disagreements over definitions make much difference to Sterling’s argument that modern life can break this physiological control system. Before getting to that discussion, though, he spends the first four chapters on a deep evolutionary history tour to trace the origins of the components of allostasis. This tour encompasses the molecular details of the genetic code, protein functionality, and ATP synthesis and hydrolysis to store and release energy at a cellular level. It encompasses the evolution of multicellularity and what we inherited from our worm-like ancestor in the way of cellular clocks, early brains, and feedback regulation between the different parts. (Side note, this is likely where dopamine was introduced as the brain’s reward signal for useful behaviour, enabling learning.) It encompasses the evolution of endothermy and the respiratory and cardiovascular adaptations enabling it. And, finally, it encompasses the evolution of Homo sapiens when it left Africa some 150,000 years ago. Sterling argues that changes to our brain allowed us to oust our Neanderthal cousins. Summarising from his book Principles of Neural Design, he gives a bird’s-eye-view of how the brain is organised for optimal functioning, what we inherited from our primate ancestors, and what we changed.
Overall, these chapters are well written and full of fascinating information, though I am not sure all of it is necessary to understand allostasis. Also, there are a few minor points I take issue with. I understand that phrases such as “a reptile evolved two new features and came out as a mammal” (p. xxv) and “At the pinnacle of life’s energy-driven complexity, perches—precariously—Homo sapiens” (p. 1) are shorthand. However, they could be mistaken for outdated linear thinking about evolution, even if Sterling’s writing in the rest of the book suggests no such thing. We did not evolve from reptiles. We share a common ancestor with them but they have been on an equally long evolutionary journey. Furthermore, Sterling strongly argues that evolution has produced optimal structures or, where tradeoffs make something seem suboptimal, optimal trade-offs. His endnotes explain that e.g. our appendix and the seemingly backwards design of our retina are actually functional, and he concludes that “[…] clear examples of suboptimality are scarce, if they exist at all” (p. 9). I am not sure I agree. The circuitous loop taken by the recurrent laryngeal nerve or the design of our throat that puts us at constant risk of choking are but two of many examples that Nathan Lents discussed in his book Human Errors. We know that evolution cannot simply start from scratch and that it reuses, repurposes, and rejiggles existing structures for new functions. Furthermore, Daniel S. Milo’s Good Enough criticized adaptationist storytelling and made an interesting argument for the persistence of the mediocre. Perhaps these are just issues of semantics and, seeing they do not really bear on his central argument, I will not dwell on them further.
Having taken the deep evolutionary tour, chapters 5 and 6 are where Sterling finally drops the payload and delivers the goods. The mechanism of allostasis breaks down when demand is excessively high for sustained periods. The body responds by shifting its operating range upwards and what used to be exceptional becomes the new normal. In the example of blood pressure you end up with chronic hypertension. Something similar happens with our reward circuits. We evolved as socially living hunter-gatherers that had regular physical exercise, where children of different ages played together unsupervised, where we learned and perfected skills such as hunting over decades, and where the elderly contributed to care of the young. Call them the simple pleasures of life but that is the whole point, they were sources of regular small pulses of dopamine. Sterling argues that instead we now try to get our dopamine hit from alcohol, nicotine, drugs, food, gambling, pornography, or shopping. And many of these activities deliver greater surges, with allostasis adapting us to take such surges as the new normal, fostering addiction. By his reasoning, the Western epidemic of hypertension, obesity, depression, suicide, alcoholism, and addiction to drugs and gambling are all a consequence of our modern, dopamine-deprived lifestyle. He will even throw in climate change, resulting as it does from excessive consumption of goods, meat, and (air) travel.
There is no shortage of recent books arguing that we are the victim of an evolutionary mismatch with instinctive brain circuits that cause us to e.g. overeat; that we have become unfit for purpose and our hunter-gatherer origins mean that we are poorly adapted to modern life. Sterling puts neurological flesh on the bones of that argument. More importantly, he pleads with us not to blame our evolutionary heritage. This reward circuit “inherited from worms […] works exactly as it is supposed to—just not for what it was intended. This has been termed a “mismatch” […] but that euphemism avoids facing squarely that “how we live now” is intolerable to a large fraction of our population” (p. 138). The tragedy is that medical practitioners try to combat this epidemic of apparently intractable chronic illnesses with pharmacotherapy—a pill here, a beta-blocker there—in a vain attempt to correct specific physiological parameters without recognizing that “the underlying biochemical and neural circuits are not actually broken” (p. 165).
By and large, I am on board with Sterling’s line of reasoning. We did indeed live as hunter-gatherers for the vast majority of our evolutionary history, and the argument of our current dopamine-deprived lifestyle is attractive.
However.
I am always a bit wary of single-cause, killer hypotheses that seek to explain a wide range of topics with one causative agent. Some claims here do seem rather sweeping, and to write, for example, that “it is sobering to notice that the growth of smartphones and Facebook parallels the growth of mass shootings” (p. 132) risks conflating correlation and causation. But more importantly, contrasting our hunter-gatherer lifestyle with “how we live now” raises the question: what of the intervening ten to fifteen thousand years that Sterling skips over? He limits himself to writing that our drip-feed of regular, small dopamine pulses eroded, first gradually with the advent of agriculture, then rapidly with the Industrial Revolution that “accelerated the process and exaggerated it grotesquely” (p. 131). Archaeology and palaeopathology tell us that the shift from foraging to agriculture was a Faustian bargain that initially took a heavy toll on our health. Our stature diminished and especially our teeth recorded the effects of this dietary change. But did we suffer the same epidemic of lifestyle diseases that we see now? Or was it the Industrial Revolution and especially the Great Acceleration that pushed us over the edge? In the latter case, it would seem there are more ways than the hunter-gatherer lifestyle to live a fulfilling life.
Are there solutions? Fortunately, Sterling does not advocate we head back to the caves and draws attention to the, I think, underappreciated argument that history has acted as a ratchet: “higher population densities gradually disallowed any return to the wild” (p. 128). One option is to work with the body’s mechanism of allostasis, not against it, through what he dubs “system therapy”, which is basically what rehab is for drug addicts. It is hard and slow, but the only way to resensitize our body’s reward circuit to more modest dopamine pulses. Preventative strategies would involve changes to modern life to restore physical and mental challenges, lifelong learning, and social relationships between the generations. These suggestions are, to my taste, rather generic and I would have loved for him to develop this part of the book fuller.
Given that neurobiology can be a technical topic, Sterling writes accessibly and makes good use of numerous illustrations to clarify principles further. I found the detour into deep evolutionary history particularly interesting, even if not all of it was relevant to the central argument. Though I am on the fence regarding some of the material here, What Is Health? is overall a cogently argued book that provides both reason for concern and food for thought.
* Have I forgotten to insert a page number here? No, this quote is taken from the first 32 Roman-numeral-numbered pages of prefatory material.
Disclosure: The publisher provided a review copy of this book. The opinion expressed here is my own, however.
Other recommended books mentioned in this review:
__________________________________________________________________
__________________________________________________________________
__________________________________________________________________
__________________________________________________________________
]]>“Good Enough: The Tolerance for Mediocrity in Nature and Society“, written by Daniel S. Milo, published by Harvard University Press in June 2019 (hardback, 288 pages)
First order of business to take care of is the obvious danger of misappropriation. We scientists love critical academic discussion, but are also wary of how eagerly and uncritically creationists will misappropriate and misrepresent *any* discussion of evolution: “See? See!?! I told you so, evolution is a theory in crisis!!!”. So, for all the biologists who are frantically waving at Milo to say: “Pssst, hey, don’t feed the creationists!”, do not worry, Milo takes care of that right off the bat.
Good Enough is a book in three parts. Without disrespecting Darwin’s legacy, Milo critically examines the history of evolutionary theory to explain how today’s thinking originated, offers alternative explanations, and provides sharp observations on how evolutionary thinking pervades many aspects of human society.
Darwin’s original sin, says Milo, was his obsession with domestication. Given that he was writing in the 1850s for an audience unprepared for the concepts of evolution and natural selection it is only understandable that he turned to this familiar analogy. Animal and plant breeding was something everyone understood. Next to farm animals, dog breeding was particularly popular at this time (see The Invention of the Modern Dog: Breed and Blood in Victorian Britain). So, both On the Origin of Species and the subsequent The Variation of Animals and Plants under Domestication leaned heavily on domestication as a model of evolution. This led to the idea that natural selection is as relentless as breeders are, to which Milo outlines several objections, arguing that all that matters is that organisms are good enough to reproduce and survive.
In the process he takes aim at several icons of evolution, including the giraffe’s long neck, the Galápagos finches (see 40 Years of Evolution: Darwin’s Finches on Daphne Major Island, a true but atypical case of natural selection that should not be extrapolated to all of nature), and human brain size and complexity, which leveled off long before the advent of agriculture and the concomitant population explosion.
The second part is where Milo offers his explanation. The history of the theory of evolution has led to a near-myopic focus on natural selection. In the process, scientists often ignore anomalies or try and find adaptive explanations – biologists, it seems, just cannot resist the temptation. In a conceptual move that parallels Brandon & McShea’s Zero-Force Evolutionary Law (see my recent review of Biology’s First Law: The Tendency for Diversity & Complexity to Increase in Evolutionary Systems), Milo argues for a change in perspective. Rather than assuming function to be the default, neutrality is. A lot of traits are simply not selected for and vary randomly.
There are two noteworthy examples Milo discusses. One, the messy organisation of genetic material: many genomes are unnecessarily large and riddled with non-coding sequences. Already back in 1968, Motoo Kimura argued that most genetic variability is neutral and of no evolutionary consequence (see The Neutral Theory of Molecular Evolution and Population Genetics, Molecular Evolution, and the Neutral Theory: Selected Papers, but see also Junk DNA: A Journey Through the Dark Matter of the Genome). Two, wide ranges in phenotypic trait values. Phenotypic polymorphisms (e.g. eye colour) can easily be brushed off as irrelevant when they are equally costly. But where traits differ, sometimes dramatically, in number or size there are energetic costs to their production (e.g. sperm count, or the bizarre headgear of treehoppers, pictured right). Such variation is often taken to be the substrate for evolution to proceed by leaps and bounds. Though clearly, says Milo, such traits are not under strict natural selection themselves, they are not being optimized. And they are far too numerous to ignore.
Milo patiently considers and disarms the usual adaptive explanations and then proposes several mechanisms explaining this bias towards excess. Invoking “conserved core components and processes” (widely shared and conserved features of organisms such as DNA replication, see The Plausibility of Life: Resolving Darwin’s Dilemma) and Pareto’s 80/20 rule, he argues that a small number (the proverbial 20%) of optimized traits are under strong natural selection and contribute most (the proverbial 80%) to survival. This leaves many traits that need to be present without needing to be optimized. For those, excess and wastefulness are the safer options; “better to be inefficient than to be dead”.
So far, so fascinating. I have often questioned why “no selection” is not considered more often as an explanation, so I find this argument appealing. That, of course, does not mean it is not worthwhile to look for adaptive explanations (Milo says as much). My main criticism here is that Milo might be perceived to conflate two concepts. He argues that many traits are selectively neutral and evolve randomly, something that others have done before him (see e.g. Randomness in Evolution). But he couches this in language that still sounds adaptationist. Saying that the mediocre also survive, that merely being good enough is sufficient, still implies selective pressures, albeit weaker ones.
The third part of the book is equally fascinating. Here, Milo looks at human society and offers some of his most incisive and sharp-witted observations. What sets humans apart evolutionarily is that we can perceive of a future, and with that came a seed of restlessness, of wanting to improve our lot. Through cooperation, delegation, and specialization we have created societies where we care for each other’s needs. The drive for excess led to imaginative brains that became very successful in ensuring survival for all through technology, agriculture, and health care.
We have achieved this now, but the drive persists, “our bored neurons crave action”. So we construct problems for ourselves to solve, endless diversions to lose ourselves in. Politics, sports, cuisine, art, fashion, science, work – all our culture, all our questing for athletic, emotional, and spiritual goals. They are all but exercises, endless loops, to give our lives meaning. Even though we have never had it so good, we continue to compete as if our lives depend on it, for without it “we would succumb to boredom and despair”. It may sound bleak, but for all those who ever wondered what the point of it all is… Now, says Milo, contrast that with the tales we tell ourselves. Our economies are steeped in Darwinian metaphors of relentless optimization and cut-throat competition, and we continue to educate our children to excel. We have taken Darwin’s good ideas and extrapolated them to many other fields where they just do not apply.
Good Enough is nicely produced with numerous carefully designed colour illustrations. On the biological details, Milo is clearly not alone (neutral selection has been mooted by others), but his application of it to human affairs is both insightful and unsettling. His ideas are thought-provoking, no doubt controversial to some, and I look forward to pushback from evolutionary biologists. But a fun and accessible read like this is suitable for a wide audience. What a fantastic book!
Disclosure: The publisher provided a review copy of this book. The opinion expressed here is my own, however. You can support this blog using below affiliate links, as an Amazon Associate I earn from qualifying purchases:
Good Enough hardback
, ebook, audiobook or audio CD
Other recommended books mentioned in this review:
__________________________________________________________________
__________________________________________________________________
__________________________________________________________________
]]>